From: | Stephen Smith, Prof. <stephen.smith@mcgill.ca> |
To: | Robert Stevens <robert.stevens@ucl.ac.uk> |
obligations@uwo.ca | |
Date: | 24/03/2009 18:18:19 UTC |
Subject: | RE: [ODG] Implied terms |
It seems (though I have not thought much about this) that if the
distinction between positively implying a term and negatively construing a term
can do in any work, it is in the case where the argument is that the court
should imply an additional positive obligation, e.g., implying a term that,
say, the music hall comes with a janitor when the agreement said nothing about
this. Even here, I can well imagine that such a thing could go without saying
(indeed, I can imagine this in exactly the kind of rental of space arrangement
just described), though I accept that it should happen more rarely. Further, the
principle that the parties should not be allowed to ask the courts to do what
their lawyers ought to have done (which has nothing to do with the meaning of agreement,
but a lot to do with conserving judicial resources), would seem to apply more strongly
in the case of implying a positive obligation.
In response to Kevin, I don’t pretend that I can offer
knock-down arguments for an implied-term explanation of the difficult cases.
The task of interpreting an agreement is such that reasonable people will
reasonably disagree about just how much goes without saying in any particular
case. Further, it is not easy to compare the persuasiveness of
implied-term explanations of the difficult cases with alternative explanations,
e.g., fairness, efficiency, because our ideas of what goes without saying are
influenced by conventional views as to what is fair and efficient. One reason it
goes without saying that delivery cannot take place at 3:00 am is that it would
be blatantly unfair and inefficient for delivery to happen at this time. So I
don’t think the debate between those who believe in implied-term
explanations and those who believe in alternative explanations will ever be
settled. (In the end, I think the position one adopts on this issue—and I
include myself here—is usually a reflection of how strongly one wants to
explain contractual obligations as flowing from the parties rather than the
state). All that said, it is important not to assume that genuinely
implied-terms can only arise with respect to matters that were before the parties’
minds. I jumped on this point because the view that genuinely implied terms
must have been before the parties’ minds is not an uncommon.
Cheers
steve
Stephen A. Smith
Professor & William
Faculty of Law,
1-514-398-6633
fax:
1-514-398-3233
From: Robert Stevens
[mailto:robert.stevens@ucl.ac.uk]
Sent: Tuesday, March 24, 2009 11:26 AM
To: Stephen Smith, Prof.; obligations@uwo.ca
Subject: RE: [ODG] Implied terms
I don't think that we can (always satisfactorily) explain
mutual mistake in terms of an implied condition precedent, and have said so in
print and so must really believe it (See A Burrows and E Peel, Contract Terms
ch 6 pp 104-106). Just as frustration cannot be adequately explained
by implied conditions subsequent ("If the music hall burns down the
agreement comes to an end").mutual mistake cannot always be satisfactorily
explained by implied conditions precedent ("if the music hall does not
exist, there is no contract") .
I think this because in many cases such an implication will be
wholly artificial as it cannot be determined what the parties would have agreed
if they had thought about the matter in advance. The court's task is not that
of *positively*
implying a condition. Rather the court's task is the *negative* one of
construing the limits on the actual words the parties have used. Words are not
intended to be absolute. So the word 'game' in relation to the babysitter is
not intended to include knife throwing or poker although 'game' can include
these things in other contexts. The word 'game' is
qualified'. Similarly in contract the limits of what has been
contracted for must be ascertained, and where the promises do not upon their
true construction cover the unforeseen situation, because the for example the
subject-matter unforeseeably does not exist, the promises do not bind.
For myself I think there is a difference between inserting
something which is, observably, not there, and construing the limits of what
clearly is there. If a term is not there I can see how it might be
inserted because it is " necessary
to give business efficacy to the contract." I cannot
quite see how we can insert something which is observably not present by asking
what the words which are there "may
be reasonably understood to mean". Construing the proper
limits of words is rather different from adding in new clauses.
Rob
From: Stephen Smith, Prof.
[mailto:stephen.smith@mcgill.ca]
Sent: 24 March 2009 14:06
To: obligations@uwo.ca
Subject: RE: [ODG] Implied terms
Although I am sympathetic to Jason' view that mutual mistake
cases can be explained (usually) on the basis of an implied (but genuinely
intended) condition precedent, I don't see that the Privy Council's statement
(which basically restates the law) proves that this is how they should be
explained.. Whatever interpretative approach is used, we can't conclude that a
particular decision to set aside a contract for mistake is based on an
implied-in-fact term without looking at the facts of the case and determining,
on the basis of the words used, the context, etc.., that the contract in fact
included the relevant implied term. At most, the adoption of this or that
test can make it more or less likely that such a conclusion is possible. The
PC's statement is consistent with concluding that all mistake cases can be so
explained, but it is also consistent with the opposite.
But against Kevin (and in support of Jason), I don't see how the
PC's statement, or any reasonable description of what is involved in
interpretation, could possibly require that the meaning of a statement is
equivalent to what was actually before the minds of the parties. If I
order some furniture to be delivered 'next friday', it goes without saying that
delivery should occur during working hours (unless there is something special
about the industry or this particular arrangement). I could, and would, refuse
delivery at 3:00 am. Yet it is quite likely that neither I nor the store
were thinking, when we made the delivery, that 'friday' meant 'friday between 9
and 5': we simply did not give any thought to this matter.. Wittgenstein
is the classic reference for the idea that many things go without saying (or
even thinking) (he gives the example of instructing the babysitter to play a
game with the children - can 'game' mean poker?), but the point has also been
extensively developed in legal literature; e.g. Langille and Ripstein 'Strictly
Speaking it Went Without Saying' (1996) 2 Legal Theory 63.
The PC's test is perfectly consistent, as it must be, with the
view that contracts that are ostensibly set aside for mistake (or
'frustration') are in reality set aside because they contain an implied term to
this effect, even if that term was not only not expressed by the parties but
not before their minds when they made the contract. (But, to repeat, the pc's
test does not prove that in fact the cases can be so explained.)
Steve Smith
From: Kelvin F.K. Low
[mailto:kelvin.low@gmail.com]
Sent: March-24-09 8:38 AM
To: obligations@uwo.ca
Subject: Re: [ODG] Implied terms
There are indeed many cases of mutual
mistake whereby an implied condition precedent analysis would apply. Cases of
res sua would certainly fall within this category. Provided there is no
contrary intention, cases of res extincta probably would too. However, since
Solle v Butcher at the earliest and Associated Japanese Bank at the latest,
mutual mistake cases are cases falling beyond this analysis.
If frustration and mutual mistake are
related doctrines, differentiated only on the basis of when the common
assumption is falsified, then it seems sensible that mutual mistake cannot be
explained on the basis of the parties' intentions. After all, it is a
requirement for frustration to apply that the frustrating event be
unforeseeable. This, of course, raises the question of what we mean by the
parties' intentions. If, by the parties intention, we mean what they actually
thought but failed to express, then it is difficult to understand how they can
intend a particular result to follow an unforeseeable event. If that is true
for frustration, that must equally be true of mutual mistake.
It is, of course, plausible that by the
parties' intention, we do not mean their actual intention (given that the event
was unforeseeable), but what they would have intended had their attention been
drawn to that unforeseeable event at the time of contracting. The two types of
implied intention are quite different. Until Stack v Dowden, the courts seemed
to consider the latter type of implied intentio irrelevant. This seems to have
been the case in contract, trusts, and statutory interpretation.
Such "implied" intention is
regarded as fictitious because the parties never actually had the intention. It
is, I suppose, unfortunate that the descriptions
"fictitious" and "artificial" are regarded as carrying
a perjorative overtone. I am hesitant to dismiss such fictitious
"implied" intentions as inherently without value. There must be
cases, perhaps many cases even, where it is not difficult to determine what the
parties would have agreed at the time of contracting if they had indeed been
forewarned of the unforeseen event. However, it is equally true that
occasionally, the conclusion reached by the courts on the basis of such
fictitious reasoning is conclusive and circular - where the assertion that, if
the parties had been forewarned, they would have agreed on such and such a
result, is nothing more than an assertion.
Certainly, if such fictitious implied
intentions were a plausible device in divining the parties intentions, I don't
see why the courts should limit themselves to implied conditions precedent (for
mutual mistake) or implied conditions subsequent (for frustration). The parties
could (theoretically) agree to an implied price escalation clause or any
number of potential variations to the contract. But perhaps it would be
unworkable to introduce an infinite variety of possible agreements?
But I digress. I think that the Privy
Council's decision remains well within the orthodox and conservative view of
real implied intentions and does not justify fictional implied intentions. This
is not to say the device of real implied intentions may not be manipulated by
the courts. It is easy enough to conclude that, on the evidence, this is what
the parties really intended but did not express when the reason why the court
really reaches its conclusion is because it feels that this ought to be the
bargain between the parties.
Cheers,
Kelvin Low
2009/3/24 Jason Neyers <jneyers@uwo.ca>
If this is right, I can't see why so many
people think that the implied condition precedent view of mutual mistake is
artificial and fictitious and is better explained by the rule of law route.
Cheers,
---- Original
Message -----
From: David Lascelles <dlascelles@yahoo.com>
Date: Tuesday, March 24, 2009 3:50 am
Subject: [ODG] Implied terms
To: obligations@uwo.ca
> Dear All, > > In the recent Privy Council decision in Attorney
General of Belize & Oths v Belize Telecom Limited (available from
http://www.privy-council.org.uk/output/Page540.asp),
the Judicial Committee (Lords Hoffmann, Rodger, Carswell and Brown and
Baroness Hale) reviewed the various ways of expressing the test for an
implication of a term into an instrument (in this case Articles of
Association). > > The Board held that there is only one
question that needs to be answered to determine whether a term should be
implied: > > “21.
It follows that in every case in which it is said that some provision ought
to be implied in an instrument, the question for the court is whether such a
provision would spell out in express words what the instrument, read against
the relevant background, would reasonably be understood to mean. It
will be noticed from Lord Pearson’s speech [in Trollope & Colls
Ltd v North West Metropolitan Regional Hospital Board [1973] 1 WLR 601]
that this question can be reformulated in various ways which a court may find
helpful in providing an answer – the implied term must “go
without saying”, it must be “necessary to give business efficacy
to the contract” and so on – but these are not in the
Board’s opinion to be treated as different or additional tests.
There is only one question: is that what the instrument, read as a whole
against the relevant background, would reasonably be understood to mean?” > > The Board referred to the oft-cited speech
of Lord Simon of Glaisdale giving the advice of the majority of the Board in BP
Refinery (Westernport) Pty Ltd v Shire of Hastings (1977) 180
CLR 266 at 282-283 where he stated that it was “not …
necessary to review exhaustively the authorities on the implication of a term
in a contract” but that the following conditions (“which
may overlap”) must be satisfied:
“(1) it must be reasonable
and equitable; (2) it must be necessary to give business efficacy to the
contract, so that no term will be implied if the contract is effective
without it; (3) it must be so obvious that ‘it goes without
saying’ (4) it must be capable of clear expression; (5) it must not
contradict any express term of the contract”. > > The Board outlined what it saw as the
“dangers in treating these alternative formulations of the question
as if they had a life of their own” (at [22] – [27]) and
stated [27] that the list in Lord Simon’s speech “is best
regarded, not as series of independent tests which must each be surmounted,
but rather as a collection of different ways in which judges have tried to
express the central idea that the proposed implied term must spell out what
the contract actually means, or in which they have explained why they did not
think that it did so.” > > There is also a brief discussion about
extent of the background which is admissible in construing articles of
association– see [35] – [37]. > > Best wishes, > > David > > David
Lascelles > Barrister > > Littleton Chambers > > > |
--
Jason Neyers
Associate Professor of Law &
Cassels Brock LLP Faculty Fellow in Contract Law
Faculty of Law
University of Western Ontario
N6A 3K7
(519) 661-2111 x. 88435